Friday, 28 June 2013

Mobilize the Unemployed by Demanding the Sharing of Work and Income



Mobilizing the Unemployed 
                                                               Posted 28 June 2013

Why are the unemployed in Canada so politically passive and disorganized?  Why are they not insisting upon employment? Why do they, and the unemployed in the United States and other countries where the unemployment rate is higher, not riot or demonstrate in the streets?1 This article examines these questions and proposes that the best method to mobilize the unemployed is to demand that the employed be required to share work, as well as income, with the unemployed.

Obstacles to Mobilizing the Unemployed

Before considering the barriers to the mobilization of the unemployed, it is important to realize that their docility may prove deceptive. The response of the unemployed to their situation during the last two centuries has oscillated from apathy to revolt. The common view that the unemployed are unable to organize and rebel is inaccurate, as there have been many instances where the unemployed in Canada and in numerous other countries have engaged in collective actions in order to protest their condition and demand remedial action.2 Nevertheless, there are daunting obstacles that render the sustained mobilization of the unemployed exceedingly difficult.
There is a great quantity of writing on the political responses of the unemployed to their lack of work and on the efforts that have been made to organize the unemployed.3 The presence of indignation among the unemployed does not necessarily imply that they will protest, and many unemployed persons are likely to be more ashamed and despondent than angry. A person’s identity as being unemployed is one from which most people without work desperately try to escape, and a negative identity can preclude participation in rallies and marches, since these events require a public expression of one’s identity as unemployed.4 There is a tendency for the unemployed to blame themselves for their lack of employment. Many involuntarily unemployed persons, especially those who have been without work for a lengthy period, are demoralized and so preoccupied with their own joblessness that they are unable to perceive that unemployment is due primarily to political factors, and this awareness is normally a precondition for collective action by the unemployed.5 The harmful effects of prolonged involuntary unemployment – frequently including poverty, social isolation and exclusion, political alienation, deterioration of physical health and emotional wellbeing – contribute to impede the organization of the unemployed. There is no national organization of unemployed persons in Canada that the unemployed could join or support. Unemployment in Canada is cushioned by state-administered measures, notably social assistance and employment insurance, which enable many unemployed persons to endure, at least temporarily, their lack of work; these benefits reduce the impetus among the unemployed to organize.
The obstacles to the mobilization of the unemployed are compounded by society’s tolerance for, and even approval of, a considerable degree of unemployment. The Canadian unemployment rate, slightly over 7%, could not be maintained without extensive public support. Unemployment has functional purposes, and the government and many Canadians consider that the benefits of unemployment are acceptable tradeoffs for the damages that unemployment inflicts upon the unemployed and society.6 The societal acceptance of unemployment is similar to, and overlaps with, the societal acquiescence to poverty; poverty exists because most non-poor persons judge that the advantages of the presence of poverty outweigh the disadvantages.7 The majority maintains a pool of unemployed and poor persons because it profits from the continued presence of those two groups.8 Richard Arneson noted that “Probably the reason modern democracies do not guarantee work to all who are willing to take it is simply that a genuine full-employment policy would favor the interests of the perennially unemployed but run counter to at least the perceived interests of nearly everybody else.”9 The widespread backing for the maintenance of a fair degree of poverty implies that many people will refuse to help the unemployed to organize. 
Canada and numerous other countries did subscribe to the goal of full employment in the aftermath of World War II but gradually retreated from their initial commitment and now regard full employment as unrealizable and even undesirable.10 The contention that full employment is a moral imperative has disappeared from Canadian public discourse. The main Canadian political parties have no economic or political policies that would lead to full employment and these organizations are preoccupied with assisting the employed. There is a pervasive view in Canada that the unemployed are too disorganized and numerically insignificant to pose any serious threat to the social order, and this belief weakens the motivation for the government to eliminate or even reduce the unemployment rate.

There is a legal right to employment but this right, instead of serving as a galvanizing instrument for the mobilization of the unemployed, is poorly known or understood among the employed and even the unemployed. The widespread absence of the awareness of the right to work (not to be confused with the anti-collectivist right to work movement in the United States which is hostile to unions) contributes to the depoliticization of unemployment.  Work is a fundamental human right and belongs to the category of human rights termed economic and social rights; this group includes, among other rights, the rights to housing and to an adequate level of income. Economic and social rights are legally enshrined within the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR) adopted by the United Nations in 1948, and within the 1966 International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR), which Canada ratified in 1976.11 Civil and political rights, including the rights to freedom of speech and assembly, are listed within the UDHR and the 1966 International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR). Canada and other Western nations have never regarded the two types of rights as meriting equal consideration and have always placed civil and political rights at the apex of the human rights hierarchy.12  Those who do acknowledge the legal existence of social and economic rights often display an unfounded uncertainty over whether these rights are justiciable rights, i.e., rights that the courts can interpret and which can be the subject of litigation,13 and consequently these persons often do not consider social and economic rights as ones whose realization implies, if necessary, state intervention. There are still other reasons that explain why the right to employment enjoys only a limited recognition.14    

The mobilization of the unemployed, challenged by divergences in the social class, age, political orientation and ethnicity of the unemployed, is further encumbered by the problem that the unemployed disagree on the solution to their unemployment. The unemployed have generally refrained from regarding the sharing of work as the answer to unemployment, and one reason is that many unemployed persons are simply unaware of the possibility of work sharing. However, the idea that work should be shared to minimize or even eradicate unemployment has a lengthy history and it usually has attracted increased interest during periods of high unemployment.15 There are two main forms of work sharing. The first one involves workers undergoing a reduction in work time and income, usually only for a temporary duration, in order to salvage their employment. The federal government of Canada, for example, provides employees in the private sector, who have entered into agreements with management to work a reduced work week, with employment insurance payments for the period during the week in which they are absent from the workplace.16 The USA has a similar program, and work sharing arrangements are present in 21 states.17 The most frequently cited and praised version of this form of work sharing is the German model.18 However, the first method of work sharing does little, if anything, to create new employment positions and thus is of minimal or no value to the unemployed. It is the second form of work sharing, whereby workers reduce their work-time and income in order to enable the hiring of unemployed persons, that should be the demand of the unemployed.

The plethora of barriers to the mobilization of the unemployed impacts the answer to the question of who should organize the unemployed. The very question may appear condescending because it assumes that the unemployed are incapable of organizing themselves. Although the unemployed have occasionally engaged in self-mobilization, they have usually acted in conjunction with external forces in order to benefit from the latters’ funds, organizational resources, experience and leadership. The two bodies that have predominately assisted the unemployed to mobilize have been the labour movement and the political left.19 However, the involvement of these two entities is replete with problems, and both are largely hostile to work and income sharing.

The Unemployed and the Labour Movement

The relationship between the labour movement and the unemployed is ambivalent,20 and has ranged from fruitful partnerships to mutual loathing and distrust. The instances in which the labour movement has been supportive of the unemployed or has tried to mobilize them have been surpassed by cases where the labour movement has manifested indifference or hostility towards the unemployed or has made no endeavor to help them organize. The labour movement’s apprehension of the unemployed as competitors for work has a long history, and John Garraty noted that the medieval guilds “sought to guarantee their members adequate work by limiting entry into the craft, a policy characteristic of organized labor in nearly every era.”21  Additional explanations accounting for the  labour movement’s reluctance or refusal to assist the unemployed include the unions’ beliefs that desperate unemployed persons could be used as strike breakers, that the unemployed are a threat to the leadership and organizational stability of unions and that the potentially radical unemployed could exert a subversive effect on the union membership; in addition, the unions, which represent primarily skilled or professional workers, often do not care about the situation of lower class persons.22 However, the presence of a high level of unemployment weakens the unions’ bargaining power with management and provides an incentive for the unions to aid the unemployed.
There are those within the labour movement who are genuinely concerned about the unemployed and who regard them more as an ally than as a threat; these unionists habitually imply there is a brotherhood of employees and unemployed by referring to the latter as unemployed workers. Nevertheless, despite declarations of fraternity and solidarity by the employed, the relationship between those who have work and those who do not is primarily adversarial. The tensions between the employed and the unemployed are always present, even during the occasions in which they collaborate.23  

The Canadian labour movement sporadically calls for the mobilization of the unemployed but these exhortations are mainly intended for public consumption. The labour movement, particularly the public sector component, is keenly conscious that there is widespread discontent among the unemployed over the movement’s employment and income.24 The labour movement’s intermittently declared support for the unemployed is usually ignored or interpreted by them as transparent and self-serving attempts to demonstrate to the public that workers are not obsessed with their own issues but are solicitous about the suffering of the less fortunate.
The unions invariably place the interests of their members above those of the unemployed and thus the resolution of the unemployment problem is never the priority for unions. Furthermore, the Canadian labour movement lacks the influence that it formerly possessed.  The national rate of unionization is 31 percent and in the private sector, depleted by a decline in manufacturing and an increase in the outsourcing of work, it is only 17 percent, although in the public sector it is 70 percent.  The public sector unions regard themselves as besieged by federal, provincial and municipal governments intent upon imposing austerity, undermining collective bargaining and extracting concessions. The Canadian labour movement is in a defensive mode and is preoccupied with preserving its earlier gains, and consequently has a negligible desire to consecrate resources for the organization of the unemployed.

The labour movement has usually been unsupportive of sharing work and income to prevent layoffs. John Garraty noted, “Given the choice between having fellow workers discharged or sharing limited opportunities with them and thus accepting a reduction in income, relatively few individuals and still fewer labor organizations have willingly accepted the second alternative.”25 The Canadian labour movement has rarely shared work and wages among its members in order to prevent job losses, and the instances of munificence have been confined to the private sector. The federal government’s slashing of the public service workforce in 2012 did not elicit proposals by the public sector unions to share work and income among its members in order to save jobs, although the rigid public sector collective agreements render any reduction of income improbable.
The labour movement has manifested even greater resistance to the sharing of work and wages in order to enable unemployed people to obtain employment.26 The movement’s frequently stated reason for this unwillingness is its rejection of the notion that employed people bear responsibility, even partial, for unemployment. The standard union response to the allegation that there are workers who are monopolizing work and contributing to the perpetuation of unemployment is the rejoinder that union members are entitled to their level of earnings and quantity of work because they have been obtained through arduous struggles.  However, the unions customarily avoid adding that the salaries of workers have often been established not with the purpose of satisfying basic needs but with the goal of gratifying various wants. The unions have obtained in their collective agreements whatever wages their bargaining power permitted them to procure, not merely those that were essential to satisfy fundamental needs. Many employed persons, unionized or non-unionized, possess gratuitous income derived from excessive work. Behind the labour movement’s declaration that it should be exempt from the redistribution of work and income lies an attachment to a lifestyle and standard of living that the movement often refuses to call into question.

The unemployed have good reasons to be suspicious of the labour movement’s infrequent calls to mobilize the unemployed.

The Unemployed and the Left

The attitude of the left towards the unemployed has been less ambivalent than that of the labour movement, as the left has usually depicted unemployment as a blight under capitalism and stated that socialism would ensure full employment. The mobilization of the unemployed in Great Britain, France and the United States during the Great Depression was largely attributable to the actions of communist parties. It is a tenet of leftwing thought that capitalism purposely maintains a reservoir of unemployed persons to lessen labour militancy in the workplace, to keep wages as low as possible and to serve as available manpower during times of economic expansion;27 leftists often proclaim that full employment and the satisfactory realization of economic and social rights are impossible within a capitalist framework.28 However, the commitment to full employment has declined on the left, and many who define themselves as leftists or progressives accept an appreciable level of unemployment as inevitable.    
Unfortunately, the approach of the left towards the sharing of work and income as a means to eliminate unemployment distressingly resembles that of the labour movement. One of the left’s objections to work and income sharing is that it would disproportionately affect lower paid workers while the more affluent ones would remain basically unscathed.29 The left also routinely asserts that the premise that available work is scarce and therefore must be shared is untenable because bountiful income held by corporations could be appropriated for the funding and creating of myriad new positions.

However, the left has other reasons, which it states less regularly, that account for its antipathy towards work and income sharing. The left has always dwelled on the clashes between labour and capital and has devoted far less attention to the intra-class conflicts among the employed and to those struggles between the employed and the unemployed. The left often decries any expressed concern about class conflicts other than those between labour and capital as a diversionary tactic whose purpose is to weaken worker unity. The left typically rejects the assertion that the relationship between the employed and the unemployed is largely conflictual, and the left ordinarily dismisses the idea that employees, by refusing to share their income and work with the unemployed, bear some responsibility for unemployment. The blaming of the employed for unemployment is heretical for the leftists who consider that abstract entities - the market, capitalism or the profit motive - or the wealthy, a category from which many on the left almost invariably exclude the vast majority of employees, are wholly responsible for unemployment.
The left generally opposes a reduction in the income of employees because it believes that only a small minority in society has excessive income and that the majority either needs the income it possesses or even requires more. The belief that many, if not most, Canadian workers have unwarranted income from which they should be separated, either by higher taxes or the redistribution of work and income, is also considered by many on the left as a heresy. The Canadian left’s disinclination to castigate the superfluous income of employees is evidenced by the left’s widespread agreement with the Occupy Wall Street movement’s ingenious but disingenuous claim that the rich are only the top 1 percent  of income earners. If the rich were more accurately defined as all those who have more income or wealth than they require, then a far greater percentage of the population, perhaps even a majority, would be deemed rich. Canadian leftists spurn this more inclusive definition because it implies that the middle class, or at least a major portion of it, is wealthy, and the Canadian left constantly proclaims the middle class to be a victimized, disadvantaged or even oppressed class. The Canadian left often fancies that the economic injustices and inequalities of society could be obliterated by a redistribution of the wealth and income of merely a tiny economic elite. The Canadian left seems unaware that the greed and selfishness of many employees, even if surpassed by that of the ultra-rich, also contribute to economic inequality and also deserve condemnation.

The left’s dislike of work and income sharing, although normally expressed as a political principle, is also due to the reason that many on the left have succumbed to the allurements of the consumer society. Many people, including many leftists, are unwilling to share their work and income with the unemployed because these employed persons dread a decrease in their ability to acquire the consumer goods that indicate their status in society. It is the acquisition and display of possessions that many people rely on to show that they are a success in life and to hopefully ensure that others will regard them with respect and admiration. A portion of these items are more properly labeled luxuries than necessities, and the desire to possess them has largely been manufactured, but the owners of these goods are afraid that any renunciation of their material belongings would diminish them in the eyes of their friends, neighbors and associates. Further, many people rarely question whether they have a right to the standard of living and lifestyle that their work and income allow them to enjoy. The position of the left, with respect to the question of distributive justice, was formerly often represented by the expression “to each according to his need,” but the modernized version is regularly “to each according to his or her sense of entitlement.”
Most people on the Canadian left are employed and belong to the middle class, and they almost always place their class interests above those of the poor and the unemployed. The Canadian left expends much effort to defend the rights and privileges of middle class workers but engages in only paltry and largely symbolic actions to ensure the realization of the right to employment. This unconscionable proclivity on the left is notable within Canada’s social democratic party, the New Democratic Party (NDP), and also within the numerous small groups on the socialist, communist and revolutionary left.30

Those people on the left who desire drastic economic and political changes in society, either through evolutionary or revolutionary means, may be ambivalent towards the end of unemployment under capitalism because the existence of people in economic distress provides these leftists with evidence for the indictment of capitalist society.31 The unemployed are sometimes fearful that the left’s stated concern for them is less due to an aspiration to end unemployment under capitalism, and more to a wish to use the unemployed as shock troops in the struggle against capitalism.32
The reduction of work hours but not of income, a common plea of the left and the labour movement, would only marginally reduce the unemployment rate and is largely self-serving because the shorter work week would benefit the employed much more than the unemployed.33                

Those without work have good reasons to also be wary of the left’s professed desire to organize the unemployed.  

Mobilize the Unemployed by Demanding the Sharing of Work and Income

In consideration of the overall negative stance that the labour movement and the left display towards work and income sharing, it might appear injudicious for the unemployed to cooperate with these two groups. However, there are individuals within both entities who acknowledge the necessity of work and income sharing, and it is with these persons that the unemployed could unite. Those employed persons in the labour movement and on the left who call for a sharing of work and income, and who declare themselves willing to accept a reduction in both, would be regarded by the unemployed as genuine and credible allies who have demonstrated their solidarity with the unemployed. This gesture by employed persons would decrease the worry of the unemployed that the labour movement and the left have ulterior motives that lurk behind their pronouncements to mobilize the unemployed.
The increased cognizance among the employed and the unemployed that unemployment is a human rights transgression,34 accompanied by persistent demands that work and income sharing be implemented to dramatically reduce unemployment, would facilitate the mobilization of the unemployed because they would interpret their lack of work not as a result of personal failure but as a political injustice, and they would regard income and work sharing as the remedy.35 Those deprived of the right to vote do not remain unconcerned or quiescent and neither would the unemployed if they were to ascertain that their lack of employment is a human rights violation for which there is redress.

Employment is legally enshrined as a human right because it is an essential activity for most people that permits survival, reduces social isolation, enhances mental and physical well-being, provides meaning, reduces alienation and allows for the attainment of other rights; the guarantee of a basic income to all persons irrespective of whether they are working, and which is often touted as an alternative to the right to employment, would not fulfill all of these functions. Moreover, the provision of a guaranteed income would weaken any commitment to full employment.36 The indispensability of remunerated work for most persons leads to a moral argument for the requisite distribution of work to ensure that everyone willing and capable of working would be provided with paid employment.37 The state must not permit employed persons to hoard work because the possessiveness of workers who have more work than they need interferes with the rights of others to work. The right to a decent minimal standard of living does not imply the right to an indecent standard of living; similarly, the right to a sufficient amount of work does not infer a right to excessive work. The redistribution of work would require a strict limitation of the number of weekly hours that people would be permitted to work, and, if necessary, the rationing of work.38 The London-based New Economics Foundation proposes, as an example, the gradual establishment of a 21-hour work week accompanied by wage reductions in order to redistribute work and attain full employment.39 State intervention to ensure the redistribution of work would be essential because many employees are too attached to their social status and affluence to voluntarily decrease their income and worktime.40 Those people, primarily in the middle and upper classes, who deliberately work fewer hours or even abandon their employment, actions sometimes labeled downshifting or voluntary simplicity, remain a relatively small minority, and most workers, even if they complain of overwork, have not expressed a demand for an obligatory shorter work week and a corresponding reduction in salary.41 
A substantial portion of the employed would have to be convinced that the advantages of a curtailment of their work and income would outweigh the disadvantages. The gains to be derived from work and income sharing would be numerous: the employed would have more time to devote to family, education, leisure and volunteer work;42 the employed would have the satisfaction of knowing that they are assisting the unemployed by deeds and not merely by word; work sharing and a commitment to full employment would lessen the likelihood of the employed becoming unemployed. The redistribution of work and income would lower the potentially explosive envy, resentment and hatred that unemployed persons commonly harbour towards the employed. The increase in employment and the lessening of class differences achieved by a redistribution of work and income would result in a stronger and more unified labour movement.43 The employed have vested interests in the minimization of the class differences between them and the unemployed.

One of the left’s objections to work and income sharing, that it involves sacrifices and concessions mainly, if not exclusively, by the lower classes, could be overcome by a demand that work and income sharing apply to all the social classes. In Canada, members of the middle and upper classes should be especially targeted for the redistribution of work and income because they could readily support a diminution in income. The justification for a rollback of the income and work of lower class workers would certainly be weaker; nevertheless, it would still be more just for 6 employees to be working at $10 per hour than for 5 employees to be working at $12 per hour and for one person to be without work.  Work and income sharing would need to be compulsory in both the public and private sectors, and in all occupational groups, save the self-employed. 
The Canadian left needs to make full employment a priority that would be achieved primarily by work and income sharing. It would be vastly more virtuous for the left to focus on ensuring that the right to employment, and other economic and social rights, is realized than for the left to fixate over the concerns of the middle class. The redistribution of work and income will appear to some leftists as only a modest reform that would fail to put a human face on an irredeemably wicked economic system. However, the unemployed and the poor cannot wait for the end of capitalism to attain economic salvation, and no transformation to a post-capitalist society appears imminent. Furthermore, as socialist societies have also suffered from the scourge of unemployment, it is simplistic and naïve to think that the arrival of socialism would magically result in the disappearance of unemployment.44 An alliance of the unemployed and their employed collaborators could utilize a variety of means to try to induce the state to cede to demands to share work and wages. If the capitalist societies were to embrace work and income sharing then the suffering of the unemployed would be alleviated; if those societies were to reveal themselves unwilling or unable to redistribute work and income then capitalism would be further discredited and the socialist alternative would garner greater support.    

The sharing of work and income is an egalitarian measure but it would not end the problem of gratuitous income in the workplace, and it would have no effect on the income of the self-employed or on the wealth of those who derive income from other means than paid employment. The attainment of an egalitarian society, or an approximation thereof, would necessitate the imposition of stringent legal limits to everyone’s income and wealth to ensure that economic differences in society are minimal.

Notes    

<!--[if !supportLists]-->1.       <!--[endif]-->Frances Fox Piven, among others, asks this question about the unemployed in the USA. Frances Fox Piven, “Mobilizing the Jobless.”  The Nation. 10-17 January 2011. <http://www.thenation.com/article/157292/mobilizing-jobless#axzz2WU0aul59> [Accessed 23 March 2013]
2.       <!--[endif]-->For Instances of collective action by the unemployed, see Frances Fox Piven and Richard A. Cloward, Poor People’s Movements, Why They Succeed, How they Fail (New York: Vintage Books, 1979); Didier Chabanet and Jean Faniel, The Mobilization of the Unemployed in Europe: From Acquiescence to Protest? eds. Didier Chabanet and Jean Faniel (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012); Andrew Richards, Mobilizing the Powerless: Collective Protest Action of the Unemployed in the Interwar Period. Working Paper 2002/175. (Madrid: Juan March Institute, 2002). <http://www.march.es/ceacs/publicaciones/working/archivos/2002_175.pdf> [Accessed 13 April 2013]; Matthias Reiss and Matt Perry, Unemployment and Protest: New Perspectives on Two Centuries of Contention, eds. Matthias Reiss and Matt Perry (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011). The unemployed also engage in less dramatic and visible actions than demonstrations in order to protest their lack of employment. For examples, see Christian Lahusen, “The Protests of the Unemployed in France, Germany and Sweden (1994-2004): Protest Dynamics and Political Contexts,” Social Movement Studies, 12:1 (2013) : 6, 7. 
3.       <!--[endif]-->For examples, see the above-listed sources. However, the scholars who study the protests of the unemployed seem to have largely ignored the question of what proposed solution to unemployment would facilitate mobilization.    
4.       <!--[endif]-->For reasons that account for the frequent political inactivity of the unemployed, see Marco Giugni, “State and Civil Society Responses to Unemployment: Welfare, Conditionality and Collective Action,” in The Politics of Unemployment in Europe: Policy Responses and Collective Action, ed. M. Giugni (Farnham, UK: Ashgate Publishing Limited, 2009), pp. 14-15. Bert Klandermans states the problem of the identity of the unemployed: “…how to make people identify with a group they do not want to be part of and how, under such circumstances, to develop the collective identity needed for collective action to materialize?” Bert Klandermans, “Mobilizing the Unemployed: The Social Psychology of Movement Participation,” in Reiss and Perry, p. 39.
5.       <!--[endif]-->Didier Chabanet and Jean Faniel consider that a movement of the unemployed cannot develop unless the unemployment is involuntary and recognized as caused by structural problems.  Chabanet and Faniel, p. 19.
6.       <!--[endif]-->The benefits of unemployment include the maintenance of inflation at a relatively low level and the moderation of worker militancy. Jon D. Wisman, “The Moral Imperative and Social Rationality of Government-Guaranteed Employment and Reskilling,” Review of Social Economy, LXV111:1 (March 2010) : 36-40. For the deleterious effects of unemployment on the unemployed and society, see pp. 41-49. The presence of the unemployed also maintains the wages of the employed at artificially elevated levels.  Society’s toleration for mass unemployment frequently dissipates if the unemployment rate exceeds a certain threshold.
7.       <!--[endif]-->See Herbert J. Gans, “The Positive Functions of Poverty,” American Journal of Sociology 78 : 2 (September  1972) : 275-289.
8.       <!--[endif]-->Ibid. Wisman mentions the “tyranny of the overwhelming majority” to describe the majority’s unwillingness to end unemployment. Wisman, pp. 39, 40.
9.       <!--[endif]-->Richard J. Arneson, “Is Work Special? Justice and the Distribution of Employment,” American Political Science Review 84:4 (December 1990) : 1136. The author argues for state-guaranteed employment based on the essential nature of work.
<!--[if !supportLists]-->10.   <!--[endif]-->For the reasons behind the retreat from the goal of full employment, see Tom de Castella and Caroline McClatchey, “Whatever Happened to Full Employment?” BBC News Magazine.  13 October 2011. <http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/magazine-15276765> [Accessed 21 March 2013] The authors note that various individuals have defined full employment not necessarily as zero unemployment but as the unemployment rate remaining below a designated target. A book that was highly influential in the formation of the attitude of Western governments to unemployment was William Henry Beveridge’s Full Employment in a Free Society: a Report (London: G. Allen & Unwin Ltd., 1944). The authors state that Beveridge regarded full employment as the unemployment rate below 3%. For efforts in the USA following World War II to enact legislation that would guarantee full employment, see Helen Lachs Ginsburg, “Historical Amnesia: The Humphrey-Hawkins Act, Full Employment and Employment as a Right,” Review of Black Political Economy 39 (May 2012) : 121-136. For an explanation accounting for the renunciation in Western countries of the goal of full employment, see W. Mitchell, Full Employment Abandoned: the Triumph of Ideology over Evidence. Working Paper No. 02-13. Centre of Full Employment and Equity, Newcastle, Australia. April 2013. http://e1.edu/au/coffee/pubs/up(check)/2013/13-02.pdf
<!--[if !supportLists]-->11.   <!--[endif]-->For a copy of the ICESCR, see “International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights.” United Nations. <http://www.undocuments.net/icescr.htm> The belief in the right to employment had a lengthy history before it was codified in international legislation. For the evolution of the idea of the right to employment, see Joseph J. Spengler, “Right to Work: A Backward Glance,” Journal of Economic History 28:2 (June 1968) : 171-96. The development of the right to employment is discussed in Jeremy Sarkin and Mark Koenig, “Developing the Right to Work: Intersecting and Dialoguing Human Rights and Economic Policy,” Human Rights Quarterly 33:1 (February 2011) : 1-42. For an introduction to economic rights, see Shareen Hertel and Lanse Minkler, “Economic Rights: The Terrainin Economic Rights, Conceptual, Measurement, and Policy Issues, eds. Shareen Hertel and Lanse Minkler (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), pp. 1-35.
<!--[if !supportLists]-->12.   <!--[endif]-->The view that Western capitalist countries have always accorded less importance to economic and social rights than the former Eastern Bloc countries is disputed by Daniel J. Whelan and Jack Donnelly in “The West, Economic and Social Rights, and the Global Human Rights Regime: Setting the Record Straight,” Human Rights Quarterly 29:4 (2007) : 908-949. For a rejoinder, see Susan L. Kang, “The Unsettled Relationship of Economic and Social Rights and the West: A Response to Whelan and Donnelly,” Human Rights Quarterly 31:4 (November 2009) : 1006-1029. It is not only Western governments, but also the Western human rights movement, that regard civil and political rights as taking precedence. 
<!--[if !supportLists]-->13.   <!--[endif]-->For the responses of the Canadian courts to attempts to realize social and economic rights, see Paul O’Connell, “The Canadian Charter, Substantive Equality and Social Rights,” in Paul O’Connell, Vindicating Socio-Economic Rights: International Standards and Comparative Experiences (London: Routledge, 2012), pp. 108-137.
<!--[if !supportLists]-->14.   <!--[endif]-->For the reasons that have accounted for Western governments assigning lesser importance to the right to work than to civil and political rights, and for the difficulties that impede the recognition and implementation of the right to work, see Sarkin and Koenig, pp. 1-42. They contend (pp. 8,9) that advocates for the right to work have not focused on the right to paid employment but on sub-rights, such as the right to equal access to work and the right to dignified labour, and this misplaced emphasis has diluted concern for the more important overall right to work. A similar analysis is provided by Philip Harvey in “Benchmarking the Right to Work,” in Economic Rights. He notes (p. 120) that many progressives have dwelled on “equal employment opportunity and the achievement of decent wages, benefits and working conditions for all workers” and have deemphasized “ensuring the availability of enough jobs to provide paid employment for everyone who wants it.”

Another reason that explains the inadequate recognition of the right to employment is the       ambiguous nature of work. The state of being unemployed signifies dependency and deprivation but also a certain degree of freedom, and the attitude of the employed towards the unemployed has consequently often been one of pity tinged with envy. There is a questioning of what is derisively termed “the cult of work,” “the fetish of work,” or “the overwork ethic,” and the critics stress the alienating and destructive nature of work. The view that work is a problem or something from which people must be liberated, although still a minority position, results in a calling into question of the claim that work is a human right. See Perry and Reiss, pp. 16-18. For a list of numerous books that have contributed to the questioning of the work ethic, see “Re-thinking the work ethic.” Undated. <http://www.whywork.org/about/features/books/books.html> For the development of the Western work ethic and for the rethinking of the ethic, see the first two chapters in Robert LaJeunesse, Work Time Regulation as a Sustainable Full Employment Strategy: the Social Effort Bargain (London: Routledge, 2009).

15. <!--[endif]-->See Fred Best, “The History and Current Relevance of Work Sharing,” In Work Sharing: Issues, Policy Options and Prospects (Kalamazoo, MI: W.E. Upjohn Institute for Employment Research, 1981), pp. 1-17. <http://research.upjohn.org/up_bookchapters/148>; Michael Huberman, “An Economic and Business History of Worksharing: The Bell Canada and Volkswagen Experiences,” Business and Economic History 26:2 (Winter 1997) : 404-415. <http:www.thebhc.org/publications/BEUprint/v02602/p0H04-po415.pdf>

16.   <!--[endif]-->Government of Canada. “Work-Sharing.” Undated. <http://www.servicecanada.gc.ca/eng/work_sharing/faq.shtml> [Accessed 28 March 2013]

17.   <!--[endif]-->Dean Baker, “Work Sharing: The Quick Route Back to Full Employment,” p. 1. Center for Economic and Policy Research (CEPR). 1 June 2011. <www.cepr.net/documents/publications/work-sharing-2011-06.pdf>  [Accessed  14 April 2013]

<!--[if !supportLists]-->18.   <!--[endif]-->For information on the work sharing program in Germany, see International Labour Organization, The German Work-Sharing Scheme: An Instrument for the Crisis, Conditions of Work and Employment. Series No. 25. 1 May 2010. <http://www.ilo.org/travail/whatwedo/publications/WCMS_145335/lang--en/index.htm> 
19.   <!--[endif]-->Lahusen, p. 11. 

20.   <!--[endif]-->Giugni, p. 11. Richard states (p. 39) that the British Trade Union Congress was largely indifferent or hostile to the unemployed during the inter-war period. For the view of the trade unions towards the unemployed in New York City in the 1990s, see Immanuel Ness, Trade Unions and the Betrayal of the Unemployed: Labour Conflicts During the 1990s (New York: Garland Publishing, 1998). For a discussion of the ambivalent relationship between the unions and the unemployed, see Jean Faniel, “Trade Unions and the Unemployed: Towards a Dialectical Approach,” Interface, 4:2 (November 2012) : 130-157; Annulla Linders and Marina Kalander, “A Precarious Balance of Interests: Unions and the Unemployed in Europe,” in The Contentious Politics of Unemployment in Europe: Welfare States and Political Opportunities, ed. Mario Giugni (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010), pp. 97-126.

<!--[if !supportLists]-->21.   <!--[endif]-->John A. Garraty, Unemployment in History: Economic Thought and Public Policy (New York: Harper & Row, 1978) p. 16.

<!--[if !supportLists]-->22.   <!--[endif]-->For a discussion of these factors, see Ness, pp. 6-14.

<!--[if !supportLists]-->23.   <!--[endif]-->Chabanet and Faniel, p. 18. The unemployed are torn between a desire for autonomy vs. their need to cooperate with an organization that has its own interests. The balance of power during episodes of cooperation invariably favours organized labour, and thus the unemployed have a lesser influence on the determination of the agenda.

<!--[if !supportLists]-->24.   <!--[endif]-->See Greater Toronto Workers’ Assembly, “Under Attack: In Defence of the Public Sector.”  September 2011. <www.workersassembly.ca.> [Accessed 5 May 2013]. The publication is a defense of the public sector against criticisms of its privileges and wealth. However, there is no mention of the unemployed and no suggestion that that a portion of the public service has excessive work and income that should be shared with the unemployed. For an example of the rejection of the claim that there are selfish and greedy public servants in the USA, see “Myth of the Greedy Public-Sector Workers.” Editorial. Socialist Worker. 18 August 2010. <http://socialistworker.org/2010/08/18/greedy-government-workers-myth>  

<!--[if !supportLists]-->25.   <!--[endif]-->Garraty, p. 9.

<!--[if !supportLists]-->26.   <!--[endif]-->For example, Stephen Jones notes that in the United Kingdom during the Great Depression, “Trade unions considered the maintenance of wages to be more important than the question of unemployment: there was little sympathy with the idea that wages should be reduced as a kind of trade off for increased employment.” Stephen Jones, “The Trade Union Movement and Work-Sharing Policies in Interwar Britain,” Journal of Industrial Relations 16:1 (March 1985) : 63. The willingness of the labour movement to consider stimulating employment by a voluntarily reduction of worktime and salary is not entirely absent. For earlier examples, see Anders Hayden, Sharing the Work, Sparing the Planet (Toronto: Between the Lines, 1999), p. 177.

<!--[if !supportLists]-->27.   <!--[endif]-->The leftists who adopt this position would be more precise and honest if they were to state that the majority in society, not merely capitalists, benefits from unemployment.  See notes 6 and 7.

<!--[if !supportLists]-->28.   <!--[endif]-->For a view that social rights cannot be thoroughly realized under capitalism, see Larry Patriquin, “The Class Ceiling of Social Rights,” Journal of Progressive Human Services, 24:1 (2013) : 66-80.

<!--[if !supportLists]-->29.   <!--[endif]-->Gregory Albo expresses the concern over austerity or socialism in one class. Gregory Albo, “Canadian Unemployment and Socialist Employment Policy,” p. 1. <http://www.yorku.ca/albo/docs/1996/Canadian%20Unemployment%20(1996).PDF> [Accessed 29 March 2013] His socialist employment prescription does include a call for the redistribution of work.

<!--[if !supportLists]-->30.   <!--[endif]-->Many self-declared leftwing or progressive individuals and nongovernmental organizations in Canada - including the Canadian Centre for Policy Alternatives, the Broadbent Institute and Canadians for Tax Fairness - express concern over economic inequality but they do not advocate the necessary redistribution of income, wealth and work required to attain economic equality or to even significantly reduce economic inequality, and their primary motivation is to maintain the income, wealth and privileges of the middle class.  

<!--[if !supportLists]-->31.   <!--[endif]-->Gans notes that sections of the revolutionary left require the presence of poor people to serve as a potential revolutionary force. Gans, p. 282.

<!--[if !supportLists]-->32.  <!--[endif]-->This fear is not unfounded, as during the Great Depression there were episodes of the left instrumentalizing the unemployed. See Garraty, pp. 194-95.

<!--[if !supportLists]-->33.   <!--[endif]-->For an example of the left calling for a reduced work week but no corresponding wage decrease, see  “Socialists Back 30-Hour Workweek Initiative,” The Local [Berlin]. 11 February 2013. <http://www.thelocal.de/money/20130211-47893.html> [Accessed 13 April 2013]

<!--[if !supportLists]-->34.   <!--[endif]-->The sources mentioned in notes 11-14 provide a good background reading on the right to employment.

<!--[if !supportLists]-->35.   <!--[endif]-->The willingness to engage in collective protest dramatically increases if the aggrieved perceive that there is not only an injustice, but also a solution. “For a protest movement to arise out of these traumas of daily life, people have to perceive the deprivation and disorganization they experience as both wrong, and subject to redress.” Piven and Cloward, p. 12. The practical aspects of the implementation of work sharing are beyond the scope of this article. However, many people are against work and income sharing not because they view the sharing as impossible to achieve but because they are ideologically opposed to redistribution.   

<!--[if !supportLists]-->36.   <!--[endif]-->For further information about the Basic Income, see Mona Chollet, “Imaginer un revenue garanti pour tous,” Le Monde Diplomatique, pp. 1, 20-21. May 2013. For detailed information on the Basic Income, see  the website of the Basic Income Earth Network: <http://www.basicincome.org/bien>

<!--[if !supportLists]-->37.   <!--[endif]-->For the moral argument, see Arneson.

<!--[if !supportLists]-->38.   <!--[endif]-->Jorgen Randers, for instance, has advocated not merely the sharing, but the rationing, of work. See Jorgen Randers, “Should Paid Work Be Rationed?” The Guardian. 19 February 2013. <http://www.guardian.co.uk/sustainable-business/jorgen-randers-should-paid-work-be-rationed>  [Accessed 25 March 2013]

<!--[if !supportLists]-->39.   <!--[endif]-->See “21 Hours: Why a Shorter Working Week Can Help Us All to Flourish in the 2st Century.” New Economics Foundation. February 2010. <http://dnwssx4l7gl7s.cloudfront.net/nefoundation/default/page/-/files/21_Hours.pdf> [Accessed 6 April 2013]

<!--[if !supportLists]-->40.   <!--[endif]-->For the necessity of both voluntary and involuntary work sharing, see Hayden, pp. 109-114.   

<!--[if !supportLists]-->41.   <!--[endif]-->Juliet Schor states “Surveys done before the crash indicate that between 30 and 50 percent of Americans say they would prefer to work fewer hours, even for less pay.” Juliet Schor, “The Work-Sharing Boom: Exit Ramp to a New Economy?” Yes!  9 August 2010. <http://www.yesmagazine.org/new-economy/the-work-sharing-boom-exit-ramp-to-a-new-economy > [Accessed 11 April 2013] However, this willingness has rarely been translated into a demand for shorter hours and lesser pay. George Rolland observed that “It seems to have become the nature of the Canadian people to monopolize all the work that they possibly can in order to collect the biggest payroll.” George Rolland, Share the Work Plan as the Ultimate Solution to Unemployment in Canada. (Toronto: George Rolland Publications, 1940), p. 10. His categorical comment no longer reflects the situation today, but there still remain many Canadian workers who are monopolizing work.  

<!--[if !supportLists]-->42.   <!--[endif]-->The advantages to employees of working fewer hours and earning less income are detailed in the New Economics Foundation article in note no. 39. There would be ecological benefits for society provided the redistribution of work resulted in a stationary economy or in economic degrowth.  For a discussion on the right to work and work sharing under degrowth, see Giorgos Kallis, Christian Kerschner, Joan Martinez-Alier, “The Economics of Degrowth,” Ecological Economics 84 (2012) 172-180.  <http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.ecolecon.2012.08.017>; Blake Allcott, “Should Degrowth Embrace the Job Guarantee,” Journal of Cleaner Production 38 (2013) :  56-60. <http://degrowth.org/wp-content/uploads/2012/11/Alcott-2013.pdf> For a discussion of the political left’s reluctance or refusal to embrace degrowth, see Serge Latouche, “Can the Left Escape Economism?” Capitalism Nature Socialism 23:1 (2012) : 74-78. <http://degrowth.org/wp-content/uploads/2012/11/Latouche-can-the-left-escape-economism.pdf>  

<!--[if !supportLists]-->43.   <!--[endif]-->It is not only the unemployed, but also those who engage in temporary or contract work – the precariat - who would benefit from income and work sharing. Gregory Albo notes (p. 272) the problems resulting from the inequality of the distribution of work: “The division of workers into those who have paid work in core jobs and those excluded from stable employment at fair wages leads to social polarization and increases the leverage of capitalists to control production and inordinately influence democratic deliberation through threat of capital flight.” 

<!--[if !supportLists]-->44.   <!--[endif]-->For the persistence of unemployment in socialist societies, see Susan L. Woodward,  Socialist Unemployment: The Political Economy of Yugoslavia, 1945-1990 (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1995), and J. L. Porket, “Full Employment in Soviet Theory and Practice,” British Journal of International Relations 27:2 (July 1989) : 264-279.




Tuesday, 11 December 2012

The Americanization of Canadian Politics



The Americanization of Canadian Politics
Posted 11 December 2012
 
 
The novel presence of the NDP as the opposition in Parliament, and the apparent stark contrast between a rightwing Conservative government and a leftwing NDP, has led numerous political commentators to contend that federal politics in Canada has become polarized between two parties, similar to the polarization in the United States. The analysts who allege a polarization has occurred in Canada are correct, but not for the reasons they imagine.
The American political system is polarized between the two political parties that have a duopoly on power, and, in the USA, the Republican Party is normally referred to as the political right and the Democratic Party commonly labelled as the political left. However, the rubric political left has a different connotation in the USA than in Canada. In the USA, the left, as it is embodied by the Democratic Party, is a form of liberalism. In Canada, the parliamentary left, as it has been represented by the NDP, has been a variant of social democracy.

It has been the presence of a leftwing party, the NDP, and its predecessor, the Cooperative Commonwealth Federation (CCF), that has historically offered the electorate an alternative to the Liberal Party and the Conservative Party, and which has differentiated Canada from the two party system of the USA. The early CCF can justifiably be called a socialist party, but it gradually watered down or discarded much of its socialist agenda and transformed itself into a social democratic party. The NDP was never a socialist party and has always been a social democratic one. Nevertheless, the presence of a social democratic party in Canada, even if it only followed a piecemeal approach to changing society and only proposed modest reforms that did not seriously threaten the status quo, did offer voters a possibility unavailable to their American counterparts.
This option is no longer present. The NDP has been inexorably moving towards the centre for 50 years, and although it continues to call itself a leftwing social democratic party, it is highly dubious that it still merits to be called either leftwing or social democratic. Extensive public ownership and economic equality, two former values that largely defined the left, have been renounced by the NDP, even as idealistic and long-term objectives. The NDP has no vision of how economic life should be organized that is substantially different from that advocated by the Liberals and the Conservatives; the party only proposes greater regulation of the market in order to hopefully stabilize it, but the NDP does not want any meaningful alteration to the economic system. The NDP’s expressed concern with economic inequality should not be interpreted as a desire for economic equality. The NDP only advocates that a very small percentage of the rich should pay a slightly higher tax, and this plea, if acted upon, would result in the prevailing immense economic inequalities remaining essentially intact. The NDP has abandoned any belief in the desirability of the equality of outcomes, formerly a salient value of the left, and has embraced the doctrine of equality of opportunity, which has been historically a hallmark of liberalism.

It is the transformation of the NDP from a leftwing party to a centrist party embracing liberalism that has resulted in the Americanization of Canadian politics. Canadian politics is not polarized between parties that offer significantly divergent political ideologies; it is only divided between a liberal and a conservative version of capitalism.
The New Democratic Party is now almost ideologically indistinguishable from the United States Democratic Party or the Canadian Liberal Party. NDP politicians justify the centrist orientation of the party by claiming that it has merely undergone necessary modernization, a euphemism for the party’s repudiation of its former values, and by alleging that the party is simply echoing an electorate that increasingly finds the former left-right cleavage meaningless.

A resurgence of the Liberal Party under a new leader will mean that the party will compete with the NDP for liberal pre-eminence; if there is no such revival, then the Liberal Party will remain the minor Canadian party espousing liberal values.   
The Americanization of Canadian politics, by which the major parties are now either liberal, in name or in spirit, or conservative, has resulted in the impoverishment of the electorate. The voters are now confronted with a pseudo-polarization between liberalism and conservatism, not an authentic polarization between left and right or between capitalism and socialism.

Thursday, 29 November 2012

The Poverty of the Anti-Poverty Movement


Posted 29 November 2012

It is an error to consider that the anti-poverty movement is opposed to wealth or economic inequality. It is highly doubtful that the movement even desires the end of poverty.
The word anti-poverty in itself does not suggest that wealth or inequality is wrong; it only intimates that income below a certain level is a problem and implies that poverty is the injustice or the evil in need of elimination. Those who refer to themselves as anti-poverty neglect to note that there is a lengthy tradition that posits for a variety of political, psychological, philosophical, moral and religious reasons that poverty is a virtue and a desired state. The conception of poverty as a good usually, although not invariably, distinguishes between poverty and destitution and makes no claim that the latter is laudable. The goodness of poverty could obviously be employed as an argument by those who reject the redistribution of income and wealth and therefore for the remainder of this article poverty refers to those who are involuntarily poor.

Anti-poverty activists and countless other Canadians, including many who are on the political left, say that they would like to see the termination of poverty but the depressing reality is that many Canadians want poverty to continue because poverty is beneficial for many persons. Many people, particularly on the left, declare that only corporations benefit from poverty and these individuals note that the presence of a pool of poor or unwaged persons tempers worker militancy and acts as a mechanism to keep wages stable. However, it is more accurate and honest to state that everyone who is not poor benefits indirectly or directly from the existence and continuation of poverty.
A famous sociological article (Herbert J. Gans, “The Positive Functions of Poverty,” American Journal of Sociology, September 1972) listed 15 positive economic, social, political and cultural functions of poverty. The contention that the non-poor may actually desire the poor to remain poor often meets with denial or incredulity, and therefore some of poverty’s functions listed by that author bear repeating. The poor ensure that there is a supply of people to perform low-paid, dangerous or menial work; the poor help produce jobs in numerous professions and institutions that serve the poor or protect the non-poor from the poor (including religious and philanthropic bodies devoted to the poor, pawnshops, used clothing stores and the police); the low wages of the poor often subsidize the lifestyles of the affluent; the poor help maintain the legitimacy of the dominant societal norms by their behavior (often stereotyped as lazy, spendthrift and dishonest); the poor guarantee the status of the non-poor (the middle and upper classes would not be aware of their higher status without the existence of the poor); the poor play a disproportionately minor part in politics which results in a skewed participation by the non-poor. The poor also provide the material for endless studies by academics, research institutions, advocacy groups and health care professionals; the poor help the affluent to feel altruistic and righteous by evoking pity, charity, and compassion.

It is necessary, as a counter to the above, to mention some of the negative consequences arising from the existence of poverty. The poor result in many non-poor feeling guilt and shame. The poor are often unused or underutilized economic resources; the poor suffer greatly from prolonged poverty; the poor are more likely than the non-poor to acquire serious ailments and are thus a disproportionate burden on the health-care system; the poor are a painful reminder of what may befall the non-poor if they are afflicted by long-term unemployment or illness; the poor result in higher expenditures for police and security measures; the desperation of the poor invokes fear and dread among the non-poor; the poor raise the specter of social unrest and political violence.
In Canadian society, the poor constitute between 15 and 20 per cent of the population and most Canadians who are non-poor consider that the advantages (to themselves) of the maintenance of poverty outweigh the drawbacks. Further, the non-poor recognize that the poor are too few, too disorganized and too demoralized to pose a serious threat to the social order.     

The phenomenon that many persons who benefit directly or indirectly from the continuation of poverty also state that they are anti-poverty suggests that such individuals may actually be ambivalent towards the extirpation of poverty. On the one hand, they state that they are against the negative aspects of poverty but is it not in their interests to maintain poverty because of its positive functions? The equivocation is revealed by their attitude towards the two types of poverty, absolute and relative. Absolute poverty, the form of poverty usually opposed by the anti-poverty movement, is income below the threshold of the absolute poverty level and often results in an inability to provide for basic needs. Relative poverty is a more a subjective condition and is the manner in which people evaluate their wealth in relation to that of others. It is often relative poverty, not absolute poverty, that tears societies asunder.
The wealth redistribution that would have to be effected in order to eliminate absolute poverty in Canada is insubstantial, although if it were done, it would barely lessen, if at all, relative poverty; if the poor were given more money to bring their incomes up to the absolute poverty line, the incomes of the middle and upper classes would undoubtedly be simultaneously increasing, and the gap between the poor and the non-poor would thus be essentially unaltered. In order to substantially decrease relative poverty, it would be vital to impose rigorous limits on the amount of wealth and income that people would be able to possess.

Those individuals who say they are opposed to poverty but who are not opposed to wealth do not want to significantly reduce relative poverty. It is only those who are anti-wealth who want to dramatically lessen or even eradicate relative poverty. Those who say that they are anti-poverty, by which they normally mean absolute poverty, usually confine themselves to advocating higher welfare rates and wages, greater respect or social inclusion. It would be wrong to completely belittle these proposals and to state that their attainment would be of no benefit whatsoever for the poor. But the funds often proposed to be given to the poor are seldom sufficient to raise their income to that of the absolute poverty level, and those recommendations basically ignore relative poverty.
Any attempt to eradicate poverty and to prevent its reoccurrence has to have some explanation as to the cause of the poverty. The view of the early left was that the primary reason for poverty was wealth; some people had too little because some others had too much. This explanation was complemented, and often supplanted, by that of capitalism as the culprit. However, the blaming of capitalism fails to explain the existence of poverty before the advent of capitalism and the persistence of poverty in post-capitalist societies. Today’s left and the anti-poverty movement rarely assert that wealth is responsible for poverty, and instead more often attribute it to a lack of opportunity, inadequate education, abdication of personal responsibilities and meager income. But most poverty is caused by wealth, and to be against poverty but not wealth is analogous to being against slavery but believing in the right to own slaves. Canada does not have a problem of poverty; Canada has a problem of wealth. Many Canadians possess more income or wealth than they need. A meaningful redistribution of wealth and income within Canada, and between Canada and the poorer nations, requires separating these persons from their superfluous income and wealth. It necessitates making many Canadians poorer, not richer.

The poverty of the anti-poverty movement is that it regards poverty as the affliction to be uprooted, but poverty is only the symptom of the real problem. The anti-poverty movement often states that it wants to make poverty history but what it really wants to do is make wealth eternal.

             

 

 

 

Wednesday, 28 November 2012

Why Does Canada Still Have Food Banks?


 

Posted 28 November 2012
 
Foods banks, which first appeared in Canada in the early 1980’s accompanied by the expectation that they would be temporary, have persisted and are now pervasive features of Canadian society. Food Banks Canada contends that there are nearly 900,000 Canadians who use food banks.  Why has their usage persisted and intensified?
It is a truism to state that people, working or nonworking, utilize food banks because those individuals have insufficient money to feed themselves. It is necessary, instead, to focus on the reasons why the users possess inadequate income, either from welfare, employment insurance or paid employment. Those who avail themselves of food books are overwhelmingly from the lower social classes.
Food is a fundamental human right and belongs to the category of human rights that are termed economic and social rights; this group also includes the rights to adequate levels of housing and income. Economic and social rights are legally enshrined within the 1966 United Nations Covenant on Economic and Social Rights (ICESCR), which Canada ratified in 1976. However, Canadian society has always attached a far greater importance to civil and political rights, such as the rights to freedom of speech and assembly, which are among those listed within the 1966 United Nations Covenant on Civil and Political Rights. Moreover, there is insufficient awareness in Canada about the existence of economic and social rights. There remains in Canada, despite the ICESCR, a lingering but unfounded uncertainty over whether economic and social rights are justiciable rights, i.e., rights that the courts can interpret and which can be the subject of litigation. However, social and economic rights are indeed justiciable rights, and state action is implied if these rights are judged to be unrealized.  
The government’s abdication of its obligation to ensure that none of its citizens lacks food has resulted in efforts by the private sector to supply food to those who are unable to purchase enough food.  However, one of the private sector’s responses, food banks, needs to be recognized as an unsuccessful attempt to compensate for government inaction. Food banks are unable to cope with the demand for food, and the food they do provide frequently does not meet caloric or nutritional requirements. Food banks have not eradicated hunger in Canada.
The rise of food banks has been accompanied by their bureaucratization, and food banks employ salaried staff. Many other people donate food to food banks or serve with them as volunteers. There has been an increasing corporate involvement in the sponsorship of food banks. The donors and volunteers do not benefit financially from the existence of food banks but those people do derive non-monetary benefits; food banks provide them with an opportunity to show to themselves and others that they are caring and altruistic, and a chance to obtain the emotional well-being and satisfaction often associated with volunteer work. The paid staff and volunteers with food banks occasionally assert that they desire the termination of food banks, but considering the advantages they obtain from the existence of food banks, they may be ambivalent about ending the food banks. Furthermore, the staff and volunteers are usually certain of the righteousness of their actions and rarely seem to question whether food banks do more harm than good.
But how could food banks do harm? Food banks depoliticize the causes of hunger and undermine the legal fact that access to food is a human right. Food banks prompt the poor to express gratitude to those providing them with food and dilute the anger that the poor might have towards the government. The defenders of food banks claim that the immediate end of food banks would deprive the poor of an essential source of food, but neglect to add that hungry people do not passively accept their wretched circumstances. Food banks contribute to the pacification of the poor.
The food banks in Canada have transformed food security into a concern for the charities, but charity is a feeble substitute for justice. The food banks, often portrayed by their supporters as noble examples of mutual aid and solidarity, are often nevertheless, to those who use them, a degrading, humiliating and institutionalized form of begging. Consequently, many hungry Canadians refuse to resort to food banks.  
The unwillingness of Canadian municipal, provincial and federal governments to ensure that all Canadians have adequate access to food is partially due to the preoccupations of those governments with maintaining the rights and privileges of the middle class. Canada’s major political parties all focus on the middle class and have only a secondary interest in those in the lower classes. The main parties are not worried about the political repercussions of paying only minimal attention to the poor, and are not apprehensive about any threat of social unrest posed by those whose economic and social rights are violated. Consequently, none of the major parties is willing to advocate the necessary economic redistribution, which would affect their cherished middle and upper classes, that would obviate the need for food banks.
The increasing and laudable calls to close food banks face numerous systemic obstacles.

The Inauthentic Concern Over Inequality


Posted 28 November 2012

In the last decade there has been considerable concern expressed over the economic inequality in Canadian society. This unease has been primarily expounded by those who regard themselves as belonging to the political progressive or left community, and to a lesser extent by those who position themselves in the political centre or right. It is necessary to question the authenticity of this professed concern with economic inequality.
Canada has always had immense economic inequalities, even if they were inferior to the current levels, and the persistence of dramatic inequality raises the question of why so many people who now speak out against economic inequality have remained silent on this issue for so long. Furthermore, those who now decry the economic inequality frequently dwell on its negative consequences, and seem to fancy that they are uttering novel pronouncements on these effects. However, the deleterious effects of marked economic inequality have been known for a long time, and most of the current arguments for a reduction in economic inequality have a lengthy history. It is now widely maintained, for example, that pronounced economic inequalities are adversely affecting health outcomes; these comments, although accurate, have been stated by countless others for over a hundred years.

The main reason why Canadians should be sceptical about the intentions of those who castigate economic inequality is that the overwhelming majority of individuals, organizations, political parties and social movements in Canada engaging in such criticism do not usually indicate to what extent they want the level of inequality to be reduced, and on the occasions that they do, their proposed decreases in inequality would still leave society marked by huge economic inequalities. A call for a reduction in economic inequality without specifying the desired amount is meaningless and almost invariably implies only a cosmetic alteration to inequality. Those who do quantify their remarks habitually state that a very small percentage of society, frequently 1 or 2 percent and rarely 5 or 10 percent, should be taxed at a slightly greater rate. These recommendations, which are based on the assumption that only a minority has excessive income, are essentially symbolic attacks on inequality and would not make any significant dent in the degree of economic inequality. 
There is a thinly disguised self-interest behind much of the outrage over economic inequality. The prominent denunciators of Canada’s economic inequality are mostly member of the middle and upper middle classes. Their common tactic is to designate the rich, or those whom they deem responsible for the economic inequality, as a miniscule group in order to ensure that members of their class will be excluded from that category; these critics of inequality believe that their class will thus be shielded from any possible suggestions that it too possesses gratuitous income. 

It is important not to equate the criticism of economic inequality with the advocacy of economic equality. The vast majority of Canadians expressing alarm over economic inequality do not want economic equality, or anything even resembling that condition. Their displeasure over economic inequality is often only political posturing. Those who declare themselves opposed to economic inequality, but who only want minor modifications to that inequality, are eager to give the appearance that they are fighting inequality and promoting equality and social justice.   
The American academic Stanley fish aptly noted that “despite their polemical differences, the left and the right are jointly committed to the perpetuation of inequality.” His insight also applies to Canada, as behind the veil of expressed concern over inequality by Canadians of all political persuasions, there lies the ugly reality of a pervasive longing for obscene economic inequalities, with the nuance that the Canadian left seeks a slightly less unequal society than the Canadian right.  

Fortunately, it is possible to discern the authenticity of the criticism of economic inequality. If the critic merely proposes an unspecified reduction in the inequality or prescribes a minor tax increase on a tiny minority, then these exhortations can usually be dismissed as inauthentic as they would maintain the status quo and tremendous class differences. An authentic criticism of economic inequality occurs not when the critic advocates absolute economic equality, as this is unattainable and probably even undesirable, but when the critic unambiguously envisages a society with minimal economic inequalities. The French philosopher Jean-Jacques Rousseau, for instance, clearly demonstrated his desire for approximative equality when he stated that he wanted a society in which “no citizen shall be rich enough to buy another and none so poor as to be forced to sell himself.” An authentic concern over economic inequality also occurs when the critic states that there should be strict limits on permissible differences in income and wealth. Plato, for example, stated that nobody’s wealth should be more than four times that of another’s.


       

          

  

The Canadian Left Needs a New Party


 
Posted 28 November 2012
The Canadian left needs a new party because although the NDP has done many beneficial things for Canadian society, the NDP is no longer a party of the left. The party’s transformation is largely due to its repudiation of two salient values of the left, namely, economic equality and a predominant role for the state in economic affairs.

It is unrealistic, if not absurd or irrational, to contend that a contemporary leftwing political party should blindly adhere to the prescriptions advocated by leftwing theoreticians and writers of the 19th and 20th centuries, or that it should slavishly imitate the attempts that occurred in the 20th century to implement leftist ideas. Nevertheless, a party that considers itself leftwing needs to have some continuity with earlier leftwing thought. The NDP has extremely little in common with the early left. The beliefs in the desirability of extensive state intervention, nationalizations and some form of employee control of the workplace, which were commonly held by the old left and members of the NDP’s forerunner, the Cooperative Commonwealth Federation (CCF), have now a only a modest or minimal adherence within the NDP. The NDP’s conception of the state’s role in economic affairs is not significantly different from that which is advocated by the other major political parties. The party now contends that the market is essentially ethical and only requires a greater regulation in order to decrease the frequency of future recessions; the notion that there is something inherently unjust, if not wicked, about the market is now almost never proclaimed by any NDP politician or political candidate. There is, to be fair to the NDP, also a widespread view on the global left that the former radical solutions favoured by the left cannot be replicated in today’s societies. Further, the left, despite its incessant utterance that another world is possible, cannot convincingly articulate how any significant change to the current wretched economic system is to be attained.

However, it is the second political value that has often been used to define the left, economic equality, that is the focus here. The early Canadian left believed that large economic inequalities were immoral and the CCF initially wanted economic equality, but this desire gradually faded and the retreat from economic equality has continued under the NDP. It is the NDP’s disavowal of economic equality as a goal, and the party’s acceptance of immense differences in income and wealth within Canada and between Canada and the poorer nations, that compromises the party’s claim to be leftwing. It is difficult to see how a party opposed to economic equality, or at least some approximation thereof, has a legitimate claim to be regarded as leftwing.

Nevertheless, there remains a widespread Canadian political misconception that the NDP is a socialist party devoted to significant economic redistribution and economic equality. The NDP is a social democratic party of the centre consecrated to the maintenance of huge economic inequalities. The evidence clearly supports that claim. No provincial NDP government has ever ensured that everyone, employed and unemployed, has had a basic income at least equal to the absolute poverty threshold, or has implemented rigorous maximum limits on income or wealth. The economic inequalities under NDP governments have been almost identical to those under provincial governments led by other parties.

Although NDP governments have in practice essentially maintained the economic inequalities that they inherited when they took power, there was a current in NDP thought that still longed for some form of economic equality. Ed Schreyer, as NDP premier of Manitoba, said that ideally no person’s income should be more than 2.5 times that of the average of the industrial composite wage. But even this egalitarian ideal has almost completely vanished from the NDP. There are those within the party who advocate that a very small percentage of the rich should be taxed at a slightly higher rate, but such a proposal would leave the grotesque economic inequalities virtually intact. The NDP now adheres to the view that there are rights to be rich and to own and earn more than one needs, yet many leftists formerly regarded these alleged rights as pernicious and reactionary. A dominant value of Canadian society is the rejection of meaningful limits to income, wealth, production or consumption; the NDP’s attachment to that value reveals that the party has reconciled itself to the selfishness, the acquisitiveness, the individualism, the hoarding and the possessiveness that the other major parties and so many Canadians display. The NDP now states, similarly to other parties, that it is simply responding to the wishes of the majority of Canadians who reject economic equality and is therefore reflecting Canadian values, conveniently omitting to ask whether those values deserve allegiance.

A call for a reduction in disparities in income and wealth is simultaneously a plea for a decrease in class differences, but the word class has almost become a dirty word within the NDP. The issue of class, which formerly preoccupied and often obsessed the left, is now only one of the myriad competing concerns within the NDP. The party now maintains that huge class disparities are unavoidable. The party, insofar as it still has an interest in class, is now focused on maintaining the rights and privileges of the middle class.

It is a mistake to consider the NDP’s support for, or sympathy with, the Occupy Wall Street (OWS) movement as indicative of the party’s commitment to economic equality. The OWS movement does not want economic equality or any approximation thereof; it wants, at most, an unspecified reduction in income of a tiny minority, and its claim that only the top 1 percent has excessive income is self-serving and reactionary because those who have unnecessary income constitute vastly more than 1 percent. The OWS movement, although often referred to as progressive or leftwing, is more accurately described as populism.

It is almost the entire Canadian left, not merely the NDP, that opposes economic equality. The Canadian left has adopted the ideology formerly employed mainly by the right to sanctify wealth. The views that there is a right to be rich, that wide disparities in income are essential to stimulate risk-taking and innovation, that limitations on income and wealth would require authoritarian or even totalitarian measures that would destroy personal freedom, that high income is an appropriate reward for talent and industriousness, that economic equality would result in an unacceptable level of economic inefficiency and that economic equality is impossible to implement have now few challengers among the Canadian left. The traditional arguments utilized by the left to promote economic equality are rarely enunciated by today’s leftists. The belief that there are rights to own and earn more than one needs is now so pervasive in all strata of society that the defense of that view rarely needs to be stated. The wealthy are often portrayed as models worthy of emulation and as possessing positive personal traits that enabled them to be rich. The manufacture of the desires to acquire and consume, the transformation of luxury items into alleged necessities, the failure to distinguish between needs and wants, and the status bestowed by wealth have all contributed to a rejection by many on the left of the idea of limits to income and wealth. A new leftwing party will have to undermine the ideological stranglehold that the sanctity of wealth maintains on Canadians.

The transformation of the NDP into a party that desires economic equality is improbable. There is no sizeable movement or faction within the party advocating economic egalitarianism that could theoretically attain majority status. The belief that there is a right to be rich is now so deeply entrenched in the party that it is unimaginable how the egalitarian idea could ever acquire pre-eminence. It is implausible that the shift towards the right in the NDP that has been occurring since its inception could be miraculously reversed. The metamorphosis of the NDP, from a reform party to an establishment party, has also occurred in other social democratic parties. The European social democratic parties have become parties of the centre, centre-right or even the right. It is sometimes advanced on the Canadian left that, although Canadian social democracy rejects economic equality, the Scandinavian forms are more egalitarian and worthy of emulation. However, the Scandinavian social democrats have also bowed down before the altar of wealth and reject any notion of rigorous limits to income and wealth within and between countries. The movement towards the right within social democratic parties has been elaborated in books such as In the Name of Social Democracy: The Great Transformation, 1945 to the Present (Gerassimos Maschonas, 2002), The Death of Social Democracy: Political Consequences in the 21st Century (Ashley Lavelle, 2008), and Social Democracy After the Cold War (Bryan Evans and Ingo Schmidt, 2012).

The party’s advocacy of enhanced regulation of the market fails to acknowledge that such a proposal will not diminish the hideous economic inequalities within the market. The moralization of the market, if it is even possible, would require, at a minimum, that the state imposes income limits within the private and public sectors (the ratio of four to one is proposed by some leftists – no person’s income would exceed four times that of another’s), but even the attempt to humanize the market by economic egalitarianism is rejected by the NDP.

A new party is needed because the retreat from economic equality has also occurred on the leftwing parties and organizations outside the NDP. These groups have also surrendered to the conservative ideas that wealth is legitimate and that there is a right to be rich; they engage in a ritualistic attack on the wealth of CEO’s in the public and private sectors but as CEO’s make up only a minute portion of the rich, those who have superfluous income or wealth, this criticism is basically symbolic. These leftwing organizations, like the NDP, reject the notion that many Canadians, perhaps even a majority, have gratuitous income and wealth from which they should be separated for the benefit of the poor in Canada and abroad. Further, both the NDP and much of the left outside the party desire economic growth, which will primarily benefit the middle and upper classes and will only increase economic inequality within Canada and between Canada and the poorer countries.

The result of the NDP’s opposition to economic equality is the impoverishment of the Canadian political process. The widespread disinterest in politics, the meagre voter turnout and the frequently heard lament that the ideological differences between the major parties are minimal are, to some extent, a result of the NDP’s refusal to adopt a leftwing platform that would clearly differentiate it from the other parties. The Canadian electorate, with respect to the crucial political question of “who gets what” is not presented with any meaningful choice, and the parties in Parliament resemble different factions within a single party.

The challenge confronting a new leftwing party would certainly be formidable, namely, how to ensure that such a party would not degenerate into a holier-than-thou, sectarian cult. But the intolerable economic inequalities require the creation of a new leftwing party in Canada.

The Myth of the 1 Percent



Posted 28 November 2012
The Occupy Wall Street (OWS) movement began on 17 September 2011 with the occupation of Zuccotti Park in New York City. The movement continues but has faded from the public spotlight. There is an aspect of the movement that has retained a popular appeal, namely, the movement’s contention that 1 percent of the population is rich and has excessive income.
But why 1 percent? Why not 20, 30 or 50 percent? The claim that only 1 percent has gratuitous income is a myth because the accurate number is vastly more. The myth is based on the OWS movement’s conception of who constitutes the rich. The movement has failed to provide any adequate definition of the rich. The movement’s assertions that the top 1 percent holds far more than 1 percent of all income and that the wealth of the 1 percent provides its members with disproportionate political influence are accurate. However, it does not follow from those claims that the rich are confined to 1 percent.

What if the rich were defined as all those having more income or wealth than they require? If the possession of unnecessary income were to be the criterion employed to designate the rich, then not merely 1 percent of the population, but a far greater percentage, would be classified as wealthy.
Why do so many people, particularly those who regard themselves as leftists or progressives, continue to utilize the figure of 1 percent to refer to the wealthy and refuse to challenge or even question this premise of the OWS movement?

First, the depiction of the rich as the 1 percent is self-serving. It conveniently avoids scrutiny of everyone’s income and confines the examination to that of a minute minority.  This portrayal of the rich as the top 1 percent enables the vast majority of the population to regard themselves as devoid of superfluous wealth and income, with the implication that they are not part of the problem of inequality. It gives the impression that only a small minority should be targeted for tax increases, not those in the middle and upper middle classes.
Second, most people, including leftists and progressives, refuse to consider themselves as rich because this would produce guilt and embarrassment. Moreover, the OWS movement states that those belonging to the 1 percent feel entitled to their income but neglects to add that so does almost everybody else. The overwhelming majority of wage earners do not believe they are entitled to earn only what they need; they believe they are earning, or should be earning, to what they are entitled, and they do not regard entitlement as synonymous with need. 

Third, many progressives and leftists have a view of the world that is derived from 19th century works of non-fiction such as Karl Marx’s Capital, or fiction such as Charles Dickens’s Hard Times. These books justifiably portrayed society as comprised of an oppressing corporate elite and an impoverished, oppressed majority. In Canada and other highly industrialized societies, this picture is no longer accurate. Despite the wickedness of capitalism, it is dishonest and absurd to contend that it bestows extravagant income only upon corporations and that the majority of Canadians are economically disadvantaged. The affluenza of Canadian society is not relegated to a coterie of immensely wealthy CEO’s. Nevertheless, progressives and leftists focus, often obsessively, on corporate greed and the discrepancies in income between employers and employees, and largely ignore the problem of non-corporate greed and the differences in income between employees.
Fourth, there has been a renunciation among many progressives and leftists of the belief that economic equality is desirable.  They support the OWS movement because its notion of economic justice also rejects economic equality, or anything even resembling that state. The movement has refused to state the degree of economic inequality it would find as acceptable. The movement has made no demands for rigorous ceilings on permissible income and wealth or for the imposition of limits to wage differentials (such as 4:1 in which no person’s income would be more than four times that of another). The anti-egalitarian movement does not contest the purported right of people to own and earn more than they need.

The OWS movement is often portrayed as an attack on wealth, but as the great majority of wealthy people do not belong to the 1 percent, it is more correct to regard the movement as a defense of wealth. The movement’s claim that that only 1 percent of the population has excessive income is not leftwing or even progressive; it is conservative populism.